“We don’t see things as they are, we see them as we are.” ~ Anais Nin
What are we that we should see such?
January 30, 2013
June 15, 2012
Let’s define an anti-embodied cognitive science.
We start, not by disagreeing with the enactivists, but by agreeing with them up to, but excluding agency. Let’s discard the assumption that the lived body is the locus of experience. That should get the party started.
Then we wait for someone to cry foul. We take their argument, whatever it is, and we examine its agential commitments, and associated mentalese. There is no test one can do to distinguish between the tumblebot and the goldfish without presuming some locus of agency. There will be many domains of relative autonomy though.
Take whatever ‘mind’ is offered, and call it the P-world. The domain of present experience. Identify the P-world in a variety of ways: Umwelt, milieu, consciousness. The P-bomb is, of course, that the P-world does not exist. It is a construct that allows the discussion of a world.
What’s the endgame? Do we no longer draw the boundary at the species? Is this the way to realize that we are the natural world? We are the world we see.
October 13, 2011
So much blood and ink has been spilt trying to bridge the gap between something called mind and something called world. The gap I seek to bridge is instead between something called experience and something called language. This we can do. And with that the game is won.
February 23, 2011
So I started working on a sketch today that links two ideas, and the combination is surprising.
On the one hand we have O’Regan and Noe’s take on sensorimotor correspondences. This is actually not far from a lot of Gibsonian work within Ecological Psychology. The basic idea is that in perceiving, we are skillfully engaging with the world, and that practiced and tuned action gives rise to a corresponding characteristic change in the sensory array. Gibsonians would say this is the basis of direct perception. Enaction-heads would say this is skillful coping, or some such.
On the other hand, we have the peculiar issue of sensorimotor synchronization, perhaps best illustrated by a group of people dancing or beating drums together. In the scientific literature, this has withered to a laboratory situation in which people tap in time to a metronome. (The horror, the horror.) This is a singularly human achievement, the very odd animal counterexample notwithstanding (yes, Snowball, I’m looking at you and the Gelada baboons). A fuller account of the basis for sensorimotor synchronization would help us enormously. It may underpin a burgeoning theory of memes; it speaks to Gibson’s intuition that the nervous system displays resonant properties; it fits with a range of specific situations, from air guitar to stuttering. All can be described, in some fuzzy essence, with a conceptually simple model in which two processes enter into a coupled form of synergy which looks like resonance within and among coupled systems with many degrees of freedom.
December 5, 2009
Dehaene has an interesting article in Edge.org on his work in studying brain activity related to consciousness experience, or rather brain activity associated with the ability to report on the nature of brief stimuli presented visually. He uses language in an infuriating way typical of neuroscience:
We can see a lot of cortical activation created by a subliminal word. It enters the visual parts of the cortex, and travels through the visual areas of the ventral face of the brain.
Now, If I have a basin of water, and I tap the side, waves propagate through the basin, but my tap is not propagating, and there is an important distinction between the wave pattern and the tap. Yet neuroscientists talk as if stimuli were being passed around in the brain. An important insight of the enactive tradition is to clearly separate between the tap and the waves, or between a perturbation to the dynamics of the organism and the effect of that perturbation.
October 12, 2009
In this article, the consequences of transparency in public life are considered. It appears that money revels the collective nature of the system. Lawfulness appears in behavior, but that lawfulness requires us to posit a limited sort of an individual. Essentially selfish, but with a limited notion of self. Revealing our collective side, once again. Brains drive those smaller units, as they generate P-worlds. Consensus will be of our common nature, and not of that which is first person.
August 31, 2009
The set of things generally acknowledged to be real is getting bigger. That’s gotta be a plus.
June 7, 2009
In considering the function of the nervous system, a basic fact seems to have gotten lost in the latter half of the 20th century, with the advent of cognitivism. Thus I’m encouraged to find, in a lecture from 1884, the following simple truth:
If the doctrine of evolution be true, all nervous centres must be of sensori-motor constitution.
The closely related pairs of perception/action and sensory/motor coordination (or constitution, if you will) are the bedrock out of which subjective experience arises. It is not wrong to say that brains give rise to minds, it is just wholly misleading. The bedrock itself is very real, but not directly knowable. Out of it arises both the phenomenal world, and ultimately, the subject/object split, that allows us to spin tales about ourselves and a world, and the relation between the two. Within those worlds, we find brains. They are part of the world revealed by Mind.
Some more thoughts on this nice article (how nice that a lecture from 1884 is available, and easily at that!):
Some years ago, I asked the question: ” Of what ‘substance’ can the organ of mind be composed, unless of processes representing movements and impressions? And how can the convolutions differ from the inferior centres, except as parts representing more intricate co-ordinations of impressions and movements in time and space than they do ?
Of course the concepts and language available to me are at some remove from this gem. But he here alludes to the elaboration (I have called it ‘mediation’ elsewhere) of the perception/action relation that gives rise to phenomenal time and space. I suspect the author would not go so far as to say that this relation gives rise to time and space, and yet, if we are careful with our words, that is what I contend. The caveat that needs to be applied is the usual one of keeping the reality of phenomenal experience directly in our sights. The P/A relationship gives rise to phenomenal space and time. Our linguistic abilities, broadly construed, allow us to compare measurements, which in turn allow us to infer a reference scale, which we then mistakenly take as an objective standard. We must always work from the phenomenal to the domain of interpersonal coordination, which in science is the simple act of measurement.
The Croonian Lectures on Evolution and Dissolution of the Nervous System, J. Hughlings Jackson, British Medical Journal, Apr. 12, 1884, 703–707.